Página inicial > Antiguidade > ennoia
ennoia
domingo 1º de setembro de 2024
gr. logoi, λόγοι, ennoia, ἔννοια, concepção, prólêpsis, prolepseis, πρόληψις, preconcepção, antecipação
The Stoics define reason (logos) as a collection of concepts and preconceptions (ennoiai, prolepseis, Galen PHP 5.3 = SVF 2.841). Neoplatonists sometimes used the plural, logoi, which in its more general use means any kind of rational principle, for concepts, that had to be deployed or projected (proballein, proballesthai) for the purpose of perceptual judgment (krinein, krisis), recognition (gnorisis) and understanding (sunesis). The reception of data from the external world is not enough for this purpose, although it was debated whether animals could manage more than this (see Sorabji , Animal Minds and Human Morals). Whether the concepts projected are empirically gained, like the doxastikos logos discussed above by Alcinous and Priscian, or whether they are innate concepts recollected in Plato’s manner, is not made particularly clear. Peter Lautner has pointed out that at Proclus in Tim. 1,223,16-26 it is the recollected concepts, because scientific distinctions are there being projected by discursive thought (dianoia), and we shall see in 3(c) that Proclus is following the treatment of recollected concepts in Alcinous Didaskalikos ch. 4. But it would be interesting to know whether opinion (doxa) can also project the concepts (logoi) which Proclus says it has of perceptibles at in Tim. 1,293,3, translated in 1(a). I am not clear whether at Hermeias in Phaedr. 171,16-25, translated in Logic and Metaphysics 5(c), an empirically gained concept of equal is said to be projected.
Porphyry On Ptolemy’s Harmonics adds that reason (logos) with its concepts can correct inaccuracies in sensory information. Elsewhere it is suggested that in geometry our innate concepts can be used to correct our empirically gained ones, Syrianus in Metaph. 95,29-36; Proclus in Eucl. 1 12,9-13,26; Olympiodorus in [37] Phaed. Lecture 12.1, 9-25 Westerink. The second of these passages is translated below under 2(i).
Aristotle , as claimed above in 1(a), allows rudimentary concepts to animals. For his theory of concept formation and his remark at An. Post. 2.19, 100al7, that after all perception is of the universal, see 5(b) below; for commentators proposing pre-nate concepts as well as, or instead of, Aristotle’s empirically gained ones, 5(d) below; for the ascription by Iamblichus and Philoponus to Aristotle of pre-nate concepts, 3(i)(3) and 5(c) below.
In Plotinus the appeal to concepts is still limited. He speaks of the need to employ concepts already available in the intellect for recognising instances of beauty (1.6 [1] 3) or goodness (5.3 [49] 3) or fire (6.7 [38] 6). He also says that discursive reason uses forms (eide) which it has in itself, to pass judgement (epikrisis) on images provided by sense perception, 1.1 [53] 9 (18-20). In perceiving fire, one fits what one receives to fire in the world of Forms, 6.7 [38] 6 (1-7). But for recognising Socrates (5.3 [49] 3), although discursive reason (dianoia) is needed, it relies only on memory and on analysing the data stored in images (phantasia).
LÉXICO: